Thank you.
Good morning everyone, and thank you so much for the invitation to join you. As some of you may know, I co-chaired the provincial-territorial expert advisory group on physician-assisted deaths. Most recently I've been working with the Joint Centre for Bioethics task force on medical assistance in dying, in collaboration with health system stakeholders, to prepare for the implementation of medical assistance in dying in Ontario.
Today, though, I'm speaking as an individual. Although the chair has advised that we should not take a philosophical approach, I will be tapping into my disciplinary expertise in ethics and policy to provide an additional perspective to today's conversation.
Over the last few days I've had the opportunity to listen to the testimony of several panels. It has been fascinating and admittedly predictable to see convergence in some areas and continuing divergence in others. Bill C-14 is fundamentally an amendment of the Criminal Code within the parameters of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms and the charter ruling, and it has implications for the conduct of health care. But it is not the comprehensive regulatory regime envisioned in the Carter decision.
This week's discussions underscore how much of the work that we are collectively undertaking through this consultative process is not just legal, although it's about legislation and proper jurisdiction, nor political, although it is part of a parliamentary process. It is also fundamentally what I would call values work, by which I mean the pursuit of a right balance in C-14 of three ethical goals: recognizing and protecting individual autonomy, alleviating or minimizing suffering, and preventing harm. All three ethical goals have been articulated in witness testimonies over the course of the last three days.
As written, Bill C-14 proposes one way to balance these three ethical goals. Specifically, as noted in the preamble, it seeks to strike the most appropriate balance between
the autonomy of persons who seek medical assistance in dying, on one hand, and the interests of vulnerable persons in need of protection and those of society, on the other.
It proposes that this balance be achieved by limiting access to medical assistance in dying to competent adults whose natural deaths are reasonably foreseeable.
Is this the most appropriate balance? Testimony in the last three days suggests otherwise, and I would agree. Witnesses have rightly challenged the definition of “grievous and irremediable medical condition” and particularly proposed paragraph 241.2(2)(d), that is, the much-beleaguered “reasonably foreseeable” paragraph.
In my brief, I recommend removing that “grievous and irremediable” portion entirely and amending proposed paragraph 241.2(1)(c) to bring greater clarity, coherence, and consistency with the parameters already laid out by Carter.
Given its definition of “grievous and irremediable”, Bill C-14 denies medical assistance in dying for competent persons who have a “grievous and irremediable medical condition that causes...enduring and intolerable suffering” but who are not—quoting from the legislative backgrounder—“nearing the end of their lives” or “on a trajectory towards their natural death”, and whose medical condition is not itself fatal.
One might argue, as some witnesses have done, that to limit medical assistance in dying this way offers an important safeguard to protect vulnerable persons who might, as per the preamble, be “induced, in moments of weakness, to end their lives”. But if, as other witnesses have argued, persons like Kay Carter would not be eligible for medical assistance in dying, then many suffering Canadians are being left behind by Bill C-14.
To paraphrase Mr. Bauslaugh's testimony from yesterday evening, Bill C-14 rations compassion only for the suffering of those who are dying. For many, including me, the balance of autonomy, protection of the vulnerable, and minimizing of suffering have not yet been achieved with this definition of “grievous and irremediable”.
There is another area that puts into question whether Bill C-14 is successful in balancing these three key ethical goals. Several witnesses yesterday spoke about the exclusion of mature minors, competent persons who are enduring intolerable suffering from psychiatric illness, and competent persons seeking to make an advance request for medical assistance in dying.
These exclusions, possibly temporary pending further study, as per the non-legislative commitment articulated in the preamble, are explained in the legislative backgrounder as necessary to protect “vulnerable persons” in these “complex” situations. However, exclusion of competent persons on the presumption of vulnerability does not serve the end of balancing autonomy and preventing errors and abuse and may, I fear, actually have the opposite effect of marginalizing and further entrenching the social vulnerability of the very individuals we are seeking to protect.
The protection of vulnerable persons turns on safeguarding competence, voluntariness, and consent. Exclusion of otherwise competent persons may be justifiable to the extent that this is proportional and necessary to prevent another injustice. Failing this, though, these exclusions violate the autonomy of competent persons in these groups and unjustly force these individuals to remain in a state of enduring and intolerable suffering.
Waiting until the fifth year following royal assent to address the results of additional study would be neither reasonable nor just. Hence, echoing other witnesses, my brief recommends that Bill C-14 be amended to establish an expedited schedule for study of medically assisted dying involving mature minors, competent persons with primary psychiatric illness, and persons who have given advance consent while competent.
I will close my brief remarks with the final reflection on vulnerability as it relates to Bill C-14. The call to protect the vulnerable is one that we all share, and it's morally praiseworthy. However, we must ask ourselves who decides who is vulnerable. Is it the individual through his or her lived experience, or is it the rest of us in society who decide what type of vulnerability matters and to whom, and what the appropriate response to vulnerability is?
Witnesses have offered different responses to these questions. Some wish to set limits on which competent person should be eligible for medical assistance in dying, excluding those who are perceived to be in need of protection or susceptible to moments of weakness. Others wish to set up procedural safeguards to protect competence, voluntariness, and consent.
Bill C-14 offers an uncomfortable compromise among these different responses, tilting the balance of ethical goals precariously away from preserving individual autonomy and minimizing intolerable suffering of competent persons.
I know we can do much better for Canadians.
Thank you.